Law in Contemporary Society

View   r2  >  r1  ...
MolissaFarberFirstPaper 2 - 31 Mar 2009 - Main.IanSullivan
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"
Line: 39 to 39
 

-- By MolissaFarber - 26 Feb 2009

Added:
>
>
  • I think everything here is strong except the conclusion. That seems to me disappointing. It rehashes language and metaphors from the essay and from Leff, but it doesn't do so in a particularly insightful way and it makes the careful and unsparing analysis of the preceding paragraphs seem less focused and adroit than they were. I'd look for a new conclusion and tie it back into the introduction.
 \ No newline at end of file

MolissaFarberFirstPaper 1 - 27 Feb 2009 - Main.MolissaFarber
Line: 1 to 1
Added:
>
>
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"

Collective Role Ir-rationalization and Criminal Conspiracy Doctrine

Introduction

I have long been intrigued by the idea of “the mass.” The notion that individuals can transform into an entirely different entity when coming together and forming a group is completely fascinating. Gustave Le Bon observed in his book, The Crowd, that “under certain given circumstances…an agglomeration of men presents new characteristics very different from those individuals composing it.” In this short paper, I will explore Leff’s conception of the mass as a role-validating force and will use his perspective as a framework with which to ask questions about criminal conspiracy doctrine.

Previously, I had only considered the mass from the standpoint of a political sociologist in an effort to understand how a seemingly disjointed and irrational force, such as a mass of people, could accomplish social change. However, Leff’s book, Swindling & Selling, presents a function of the mass distinct from its ability to get things done in a political sense.

Leff’s Conception of the Mass

Leff notes that a con executed using a “kindly old gentleman” instead of a religious figure would not be as successful as moving the pitch “from the implausible to the impossible” (61). By adding the divine element of “God,” the pitch “becomes persuasive” (61). It stays persuasive at least partly due to the role of the mass in the Godcon. Leff explains:

The marks/players can then intensify their belief and validate their roles by looking at each other. ...it is much easier to believe (to the point of being almost wholly unable to disbelieve, even in the face of large quantities of dissonant evidence) when a mass of people all around you are believing what you believe, openly and ostentatiously (62).

Role Irrationalization

For Leff, then, the mass plays an important function in the human actor’s rationalization - or perhaps irrationalization - of his role in the Godcon. The presence of others creates a new force that helps an actor turn what Leff considers an impossible scenario into a winning lottery ticket. Durkheim, in his work Elementary Forms of Religious Life, called this energy which can cause people to act differently in a crowd than they might as deliberate individuals “collective effervescence.” Through the mass, Durkheim explains, an idea “becomes independent of every individual consciousness; it rises above all particular minds and events. It is a law whose value depends upon no person” (218).

Collective Attitudes and Conspiracy Doctrine

New implications of role irrationalization began to dawn on me last week when my criminal law class approached the doctrine surrounding conspiracy. The Model Penal Code recognizes that conspiracy is an inchoate crime meant to reach preparatory conduct. Comment to S. 5.03 at 387 (1985). The MPC justifies the punishment of an actor for something he has not already done, or something that he has abandoned or denounced, by invoking the need to “strik[e] against the special danger incident to group activity.” Id. The Supreme Court corroborated this perspective in United States v. Jimenez Recio , noting that such group criminality “decreases the probability that the individuals involved will depart from their path of criminality.” 537 U.S. 270 (2003), quoting Callanan v. United States, 364 U.S. 587, 593-594 (1961). Like the parishioners in the Godcon, persons contemplating committing a crime together are assumed in conspiracy doctrine, as Leff would say, to “intensify their belief and validate their roles by looking at each other.”

Implications for the Criminal Justice System

Given Leff’s perspective, it makes sense for criminal punishment to recognize the dangerousness of role-affirming in group criminality. However, it does not seem to sit well with a fundamental aspect of culpability built into our criminal justice system that recognizes the individuality and personal blameworthiness of the offender. This is particularly important in criminal cases, where the stakes can involve life or death, and almost inevitably result in a social stigma that functions to turn the rest of society into an incarcerating institution. Our criminal justice system, at least in theory, is not Durkheim's "law whose value depends upon no person."

The New York Court of Appeals, rejecting the Pinkerton doctrine that attributed the acts of one conspirator in furtherance of the conspiracy to all conspirators, explains, “It is repugnant to our system of jurisprudence, where guilt is generally personal to the defendant, ...to impose punishment, not for the socially harmful agreement to which the defendant is a party, but for the substantive offenses in which he did not participate.” People v. Mcgee, 399 N.E.2d 1177, 1181-1182 (1979).

Certainly, it may be questionable to compare a conspiracy of two people to Leff’s example of marks in a Godcon. Still, an examination of “somewhat typical” conspiracy cases pointed to a number of conspiracies in which twelve, twenty-one, even twenty-six conspiracy defendants were involved. Paul Marcus, Criminal Conspiracy Law, 1 Wm. & Mary Bill Rits. J. 1, 8-11 (1992). The comparison may not be that far off.

Conclusion

Where does this leave us? Are government prosecutors placed in the role of Godconmen, swindling defendants by charging them with the crime of role-validation? Have conspiracy defendants earned this loss of individuality as a result of their conspiratorial actions? Do we think they deserve to stand outside the First National Bank at closing time, realizing their mistake and wishing they were dead?

As a person interested in reforming the effectiveness of the criminal justice system, conspiracy doctrine presents a tangle of problems as it seems to ask prosecutors whether the social benefits of getting conspirators “off the streets” and into an institution are worth the human costs of de-individualization of individual action. I’m not at the point where I can tie a neat bow around this package yet, but I’m looking forward to exploring it further.


Word Count: 967 (not including TOC, HTML, or this "Word Count" line)

-- By MolissaFarber - 26 Feb 2009


Revision 2r2 - 31 Mar 2009 - 16:15:44 - IanSullivan
Revision 1r1 - 27 Feb 2009 - 00:01:10 - MolissaFarber
This site is powered by the TWiki collaboration platform.
All material on this collaboration platform is the property of the contributing authors.
All material marked as authored by Eben Moglen is available under the license terms CC-BY-SA version 4.
Syndicate this site RSSATOM